|
Various books are coming out to commemorate the millennium.... describing the highlights of the math we've done so far, and laying out grand dreams for the future. The American Mathematical Society has come out with one:
1) Mathematics: Frontiers and Perspectives, edited by Vladimir Arnold, Michael Atiyah, Peter Lax and Barry Mazur, AMS, Providence, Rhode Island, 2000.
This contains 30 articles by bigshots like Chern, Connes, Donaldson, Jones, Lions, Manin, Mumford, Penrose, Smale, Vafa, Wiles and Witten. I haven't actually read it yet, but I want to get ahold of it.
Springer Verlag is coming out with one, too:
2) Mathematics Unlimited: 2001 and Beyond, edited by Bjorn Engquist and Wilfried Schmid, Springer Verlag, New York, 2000.
It should appear in the fall.
I don't know what the physicists are doing along these lines. The American Physical Society has a nice timeline of 20th century physics on their website:
3) The American Physical Society: A Century of Physics, available at http://timeline.aps.org/APS/home_HighRes.html
But I don't see anything about books.
One reason I haven't been doing many This Week's Finds lately is that I've been buying and then moving into a new house. Another is that James Dolan and I have been busily writing our own millennial pontifications, which will appear in the Springer-Verlag book:
4) John Baez and James Dolan, From finite sets to Feynman diagrams, preprint available as math.QA/0004133
So let me talk about this stuff a bit....
As usual, the underlying theme of this paper is categorification. I've talked about this a lot already - e.g. in "week121" - so I'll assume you remember that when we categorify, we use this analogy:
SET THEORY CATEGORY THEORY elements objects equations between elements isomorphisms between objects sets categories functions functors equations between functions natural isomorphisms between functorsto take interesting equations and see them as shorthand for even more interesting isomorphisms.
To take a simple example, consider the laws of basic arithmetic, like a+b = b+a or a(b+c) = ab+ac. We usually think of these as equations between elements of the set of natural numbers. But really they arise from isomorphisms between objects of the category of finite sets.
For example, if we have finite sets a and b, and we use a+b to denote their disjoint union, then there is a natural isomorphism between a+b and b+a. Moreover, this isomorphism is even sort of interesting! For example, suppose we use 1 to denote a set consisting of one dot, and 2 to denote a set of two dots. Then the natural isomorphism between 1+2 and 2+1 can be visualized as the process of passing one dot past two, like this:
. . . \ / / \ / / \ / / / / / \ / / / / / \ / / \ / / \ / / \ . . .This may seem like an excessively detailed "picture proof" that 1+2 indeed equals 2+1, perhaps suitable for not-too-bright kindergarteners. But in fact it's just a hop, skip and a jump from here to heavy-duty stuff like the homotopy groups of spheres. I sketched how this works in "week102" so I won't do so again here. The point is, after we categorify, elementary math turns out to be pretty powerful!
Now, let me make this idea of "categorifying the natural numbers" a bit more precise. Let FinSet stand for the category whose objects are finite sets and whose morphisms are functions between these. If we "decategorify" this category by forming the set of isomorphism classes of objects, we get N, the natural numbers.
All the basic arithmetic operations on N come from operations on FinSet. I've already noted how addition comes from disjoint union. Disjoint union is a special case of what category theorists call the "coproduct", which makes sense for a bunch of categories - see "week99" for the general definition. Similarly, multiplication comes from the Cartesian product of finite sets, which is a special case of what category theorists call the "product". To get the definition of a product, you just take the definition of a coproduct and turn all the arrows around. There are also nice category-theoretic interpretations of the numbers 0 and 1, and all the basic laws 0, 1, addition and multiplication. Exponentiation too!
Combinatorists have lots of fun thinking about how to take equations in N and prove them using explicite isomorphisms in FinSet - they call such a proof a "bijective proof". To read more about this, try:
5) James Propp and David Feldman, Producing new bijections from old, Adv. Math. 113 (1995), 1-44. Also available at http://www.math.wisc.edu/~propp/articles.html
6) John Conway and Peter Doyle, Division by three. Available at http://math.dartmouth.edu/~doyle/docs/three/
The latter article studies this question: if I give you an isomorphism between 3x and 3y, can you construct a isomorphism between x and y? Here of course x and y are finite sets, 3 is any 3-element set, and multiplication means Cartesian product. Of course you can prove an isomorphism exists, but can you construct one in a natural way - i.e., without making any random choices? The history of this puzzle turns out to be very interesting. But I don't want to give away the answer! See if you can do it or not.
Anyway, having categorified the natural numbers, we might be inclined to go on and categorify the integers. Can we do it? In other words: can we find something like the category of finite sets that includes "sets with a negative number of elements"? There turns out be an interesting literature on this subject:
7) Daniel Loeb, Sets with a negative number of elements, Adv. Math. 91 (1992), 64-74.
8) S. Schanuel, Negative sets have Euler characteristic and dimension, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 1488, Springer Verlag, Berlin, 1991, pp. 379-385.
9) James Propp, Exponentiation and Euler measure, available as math.CO/0204009.
10) Andre Joyal, Regle des signes en algebre combinatoire, Comptes Rendus Mathematiques de l'Academie des Sciences, La Societe Royale du Canada, VII (1985), 285-290.
See also "week102" for more....
But I don't want to talk about negative sets right now! Instead, I want to talk about fractional sets. It may seem odd to tackle division before subtraction, but historically, the negative numbers were invented quite a bit after the nonnegative rational numbers. Apparently half an apple is easier to understand than a negative apple! This suggests that perhaps `sets with fractional cardinality' are simpler than `sets with negative cardinality'.
The key is to think carefully about the meaning of division. The usual way to get half an apple is to chop one into "two equal parts". Of course, the parts are actually NOT EQUAL - if they were, there would be only one part! They are merely ISOMORPHIC. This suggests that categorification will be handy.
Indeed, what we really have is a Z/2 symmetry group acting on the apple which interchanges the two isomorphic parts. In general, if a group G acts on a set S, we can "divide" the set by the group by taking the quotient S/G, whose points are the orbits of the action. If S and G are finite and G acts freely on S, this construction really corresponds to division, since the cardinality |S/G| is equal to |S|/|G|. However, it is crucial that the action be free.
For example, why is 6/2 = 3? We can take a set S consisting of six dots in a row:
o o o o o olet G = Z/2 act freely by reflections, and identify all the elements in each orbit to obtain 3-element set S/G. Pictorially, this amounts to folding the set S in half, so it is not surprising that |S/G| = |S|/|G| in this case. Unfortunately, if we try a similar trick starting with a 5-element set:
o o o o oit fails miserably! We don't obtain a set with 2.5 elements, because the group action is not free: the point in the middle gets mapped to itself. So to define "sets with fractional cardinality", we need a way to count the point in the middle as "half a point".
To do this, we should first find a better way to define the quotient of S by G when the action fails to be free. Following the policy of replacing equations by isomorphisms, let us define the "weak quotient" S//G to be the category with elements of S as its objects, with a morphism g: s → s' whenever g(s) = s', and with composition of morphisms defined in the obvious way.
Next, let us figure out a good way to define the "cardinality" of a category. Pondering the examples above leads us to the following recipe: for each isomorphism class of objects we pick a representative x and compute the reciprocal of the number of automorphisms of this object; then we sum over isomorphism classes.
It is easy to see that with this definition, the point in the middle of the previous picture gets counted as `half a point' because it has two automorphisms, so we get a category with cardinality 2.5. In general,
|S//G| = |S|/|G|
whenever G is a finite group acting on a finite set S. This formula is a simplified version of `Burnside's lemma', so-called because it is due to Cauchy and Frobenius. Burnside's lemma gives the cardinality of the ordinary quotient. But the weak quotient is nicer, so Burnside's lemma simplifies when we use weak quotients.
Now, the formula for the cardinality of a category makes sense even for some categories that have infinitely many objects - all we need is for the sum to make sense. So let's try to compute the cardinality of the category of finite sets! Since any n-element set has n! automorphisms (i.e. permutations), we get following marvelous formula:
|FinSet| = e
This turns out to explain lots of things about the number e.
Now, a category all of whose morphisms are isomorphisms is called a "groupoid". Any category C has an underlying groupoid C0 with the same objects but only the isomorphisms as morphisms. The cardinality of a category C always equals that of its underlying groupoid C0. This suggests that this notion should really be called "groupoid cardinality. If you're a fan of n-categories, this suggests that we should generalize the concept of cardinality to n-groupoids, or even ω-groupoids. And luckily, we don't need to understand ω-groupoids very well to try our hand at this! Omega-groupoids are supposed to be an algebraic way of thinking about topological spaces up to homotopy. Thus we just need to invent a concept of the `cardinality' of a topological space which has nice formal properties and which agrees with the groupoid cardinality in the case of homotopy 1-types. In fact, this is not hard to do. We just need to use the homotopy groups πk(X) of the space X.
So: let's define the "homotopy cardinality" of a topological space X to be the alternating product
|X| = |π1(X)|-1 |π2(X)| |π3(X)|-1 ....
when X is connected and the product converges; if X is not connected, let's define its homotopy cardinality to be the sum of the homotopy cardinalities of its connected components, when the sum converges. We call spaces with well-defined homotopy cardinality "tame". The disjoint union or Cartesian product of tame spaces is again tame, and we have
|X + Y| = |X| + |Y| ,
|X × Y| = |X| × |Y|
just as you would hope.
Even better, homotopy cardinality gets along well with fibrations, which we can think of as `twisted products' of spaces. Namely, if
F → X → B
is a fibration and the base space B is connected, we have
|X| = |F| × |B|
whenever two of the three spaces in question are tame (which implies the tameness of the third).
As a fun application of this fact, recall that any topological group G has a "classifying space" BG, meaning a space with a principal G-bundle over it
G → EG → BG
whose total space EG is contractible. I described how to construct the classifying space in "week117", at least in the case of a discrete group G, but I didn't say much about why it's so great. The main reason it's great is that any G-bundle over any space is a pullback of the bundle EG over BG. But right now, what I want to note is that since EG is contractible it is tame, and |EG| = 1. Thus G is tame if and only if BG is, and
|BG| = 1 / |G|
so we can think of BG as the "reciprocal" of G!
This idea is already lurking behind the usual approach to "equivariant cohomology". Suppose X is a space on which the topological group G acts. When the action of G on X is free, it is fun to calculate cohomology groups (and other invariants) of the quotient space X/G. When the action is not free, this quotient can be very pathological, so people usually replace it by the "homotopy quotient" X//G, which is defined as (EG x X)/G. This is like the ordinary quotient but with equations replaced by homotopies. And there is a fibration
X → X//G → BG ,
so when X and G are tame we have
|X//G| = |X| × |BG| = |X|/|G|
just as you would hope!
Now in the paper, Jim and I go on to talk about how all these ideas can be put to use to give a nice explanation of the combinatorics of Feynman diagrams. But I don't want to explain all that stuff here - then you wouldn't need to read the paper! Instead, I just want to point out something mysterious about homotopy cardinality.
Homotopy cardinality is formally very similar to Euler characteristic. The Euler characteristic χ(X) is given by the alternating sum
χ(X) = dim(H0(X)) - dim(H1(X)) + dim(H2(X)) - ....
whenever the sum converges, where Hn(X) is a vector space over the rational numbers called the nth rational homology group of X. Just as for homotopy cardinality, we have
χ(X + Y) = χ(X) + χ(Y),
χ(X × Y) = χ(X) × χ(Y)
and more generally, whenever
F → X → B
is a fibration and the base space B is connected, we have
χ(X) = χ(F) × χ(B)
whenever any two of the spaces have well-defined Euler characteristic, which implies that the third does too (unless I'm confused).
So Euler characteristic is a lot like homotopy cardinality. But not many spaces have both well-defined homotopy cardinality and well-defined Euler characteristic. So they're like Jekyll and Hyde - you hardly ever see them in the same place at the same time, so you can't tell if they're really the same guy.
But there are some weird ways to try to force the issue and compute both quantities for certain spaces. For example, suppose G is a finite group. Then we can build BG starting from a simplicial set with 1 nondegenerate 0-simplex, |G|-1 nondegenerate 1-simplices, (|G|-1)2 nondegenerate 2-simplices, and so on. If there were only finitely many nondegenerate simplices of all dimensions, we could compute the Euler characteristic of this space as the alternating sum of the numbers of such simplices. So let's try doing that here! We get:
c(BG) = 1 - (|G|-1) + (|G|-1)2 - ....
Of course the sum diverges, but if we go ahead and use the geometric formula anyway, we get
c(BG) = 1/|G|
which matches our previous (rigorous) result that
|BG| = 1/|G|
So maybe they're the same after all! There are similar calculations like this in James Propp's paper "Exponentiation and Euler characteristic", referred to above... though he uses a slightly different notion of Euler characteristic, due to Schanuel. Clearly something interesting is going on with these "divergent Euler characteristics". For appearances of this sort of thing in physics, see:
11) Matthias Blau and George Thompson, N = 2 topological gauge theory, the Euler characteristic of moduli spaces, and the Casson invariant, Comm. Math. Phys. 152 (1993), 41-71.
and the references therein. (I discussed this paper a bit in "week51".)
However, there are still challenging tests to the theory that homotopy cardinality and Euler characteristic are secretly the same. Here's a puzzle due to James Dolan. Consider a Riemann surface of genus g > 1. Such a surface has Euler characteristic 2 - 2g, but such a surface also has vanishing homotopy groups above the first, which implies that it's BG for G equal to its fundamental group. If homotopy cardinality and Euler characteristic were the same, this would imply
|G| = 1/|BG| = 1/c(S) = 1/(2 - 2g)
But the fundamental group G is infinite! What's going on?
Well, I'm actually sort of glad that 1/(2 - 2g) is negative. Sometimes a divergent series of positive integers can be cleverly summed up to give a negative number. The simplest example is the geometric series
1 + 2 + 4 + 8 + 16 + ... = 1/(1 - 2) = -1
but in "week126" I talked about a more sophisticated example that is very important in string theory:
1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 + ... = ζ(-1) = -1/12
So maybe some similar trickery can be used to count the elements of G and get a divergent sum that can be sneakily evaluated to obtain 1/(2 - 2g). Of course, even if we succeed in doing this, the skeptics will rightly question the significance of such tomfoolery. But there is sometimes a lot of profound truth lurking in these bizarre formal manipulations, and sometimes if you examine what's going on carefully enough, you can discover cool stuff.
To wrap up, let me mention an interesting paper on the foundations of categorification:
12) Claudio Hermida, From coherent structures to universal properties, available at http://www.cs.math.ist.utl.pt/cs/s84/claudio.html
and also two papers about 2-groupoids and topology:
13) K. A. Hardie, K. H. Kamps, R. W. Kieboom, A homotopy bigroupoid of a topological space, in: Categorical Methods in Algebra and Topology, pp. 209-222, Mathematik-Arbeitspapiere 48, Universitaet Bremen, 1997. Appl. Categ. Structures, to appear.
K. A. Hardie, K. H. Kamps, R. W. Kieboom, A homotopy 2-groupoid of a Hausdorff space, preprint.
I would talk about these if I had the energy, but it's already past my bed-time. Good night!
Addenda: Toby Bartels had some interesting things to say about this issue of This Week's Finds. Here is my reply, which quotes some of his remarks....
Later, my wish above was granted by Laurent Bartholdi and Danny Ruberman! People have already figured out how to count the number of elements in the fundamental group of a Riemann surface, resum, and get 1/(2 - 2g) in a nice way. Here are two references:Toby Bartels (toby@ugcs.caltech.edu) wrote: >>3) The American Physical Society: A Century of Physics, available >>at http://timeline.aps.org/APS/home_HighRes.html >I like how they make the famous picture of Buzz Aldrin, >the one that everyone thinks is a picture of Neil Armstrong, >into a picture of Neil Armstrong after all: >"Here he is reflected in Buzz Aldrin's visor.".Heh. Sounds like something a doting grandmother would say!>> 5) John Conway and Peter Doyle, Division by three. >> http://math.dartmouth.edu/~doyle/docs/three/three/three.html >>The latter article studies this question: if I give you an isomorphism >>between 3x and 3y, can you construct a isomorphism between x and y? >The answer must be something that won't work >if 3 is replaced by an infinite cardinal. >That said, I can't even figure out how to divide by 2! >If I take the 3 copies of X or Y and put them on top of each other, >I get a finite, 2coloured, 3valent, nonsimple, undirected graph. >I remember from combinatorics that the 2 colours of >a finite, 2coloured, simple, undirected graph of fixed valency >are equipollent, but I can't remember the bijective proof. >(Presumably it can be adopted to nonsimple graphs.)It's a tricky business. Let me quote from the above article:History
A proof that it is possible to divide by two was presented by Bernstein in his Inaugural Dissertation of 1901, which appeared in Mathematische Annallen in 1905; Bernstein also indicated how to extend his results to division by any finite n, but we are not aware of anyone other than Bernstein himself who ever claimed to understand this argument. In 1922 Sierpinski published a simpler proof of division by two, and he worked hard to extend his method to division by three, but never succeeded.
In 1927 Lindenbaum and Tarski announced, in an infamous paper that contained statements (without proof) of 144 theorems of set theory, that Lindenbaum had found a proof of division by three. Their failure to give any hint of a proof must have frustrated Sierpinski, for it appears that twenty years later he still did not know how to divide by three. Finally, in 1949, in a paper `dedicated to Professor Waclaw Sierpinski in celebration of his forty years as teacher and scholar', Tarski published a proof. In this paper, Tarski explained that unfortunately he couldn't remember how Lindenbaum's proof had gone, except that it involved an argument like the one Sierpinski had used in dividing by two, and another lemma, due to Tarski, which we will describe below. Instead of Lindenbaum's proof, he gave another.
Now when we began the investigations reported on here, we were aware that there was a proof in Tarski's paper, and Conway had even pored over it at one time or another without achieving enlightenment. The problem was closely related to the kind of question John had looked at in his thesis, and it was also related to work that Doyle had done in the field of bijective combinatorics. So we decided that we were going to figure out what the heck was going on. Without too much trouble we figured out how to divide by two. Our solution turned out to be substantially equivalent to that of Sierpinski, though the terms in which we will describe it below will not much resemble Sierpinski's. We tried and tried and tried to adapt the method to the case of dividing by three, but we kept getting stuck at the same point in the argument. So finally we decided to look at Tarski's paper, and we saw that the lemma Tarski said Lindenbaum had used was precisely what we needed to get past the point we were stuck on! So now we had a proof of division by three that combined an argument like that Sierpinski used in dividing by two with an appeal to Tarski's lemma, and we figured we must have hit upon an argument very much like that of Lindenbaum's. This is the solution we will describe here: Lindenbaum's argument, after 62 years.
>>So: let's define the "homotopy cardinality" of a topological space X to >>be the alternating product |X| = \prod_{i>0} |π_i(X)|^{(-1)^i} >>when X is connected and the product converges; >What about divergence to 0? >If π_i(X) is infinite for some odd i but no even i, >can we say |X| is 0?Well, we can, but we might regret it later. In a sense 0 is no better than ∞ when one is doing products, so if you allow 0 as a legitimate value for a homotopy cardinality, you should allow ∞, but if you allow both, you get in trouble when you try to multiply them. This dilemma is familiar from the case of infinite sums (where +∞ and -∞ are the culprits), and the resolution seems to be either:or
- disallow both 0 and ∞ as legitimate answers for the above product,
- allow both but then be extra careful when stating your theorems so that you don't run into problems.
>>As a fun application of this fact, recall that any topological group G >>has a "classifying space" BG, meaning a space with a principal G-bundle >>over it G → EG → BG >>whose total space EG is contractible. I described how to construct >>the classifying space in "week117", at least in the case of a discrete >>group G, but I didn't say much about why it's so great. The main >>reason it's great is that any G-bundle over any space is a pullback >>of the bundle EG over BG. But right now, what I want to note is that >>since EG is contractible it is tame, and |EG| = 1. Thus G is tame if >>and only if BG is, and |BG| = 1 / |G|, >>so we can think of BG as the `reciprocal' of G! >OTOH, G is already a kind of reciprocal of itself. >If G is a discrete group, it's a topological space >with |G|homotopy = |G|set. >But G is also a groupoid with 1 object, >and |G|groupoid = 1 / |G|set. >So, |G|homotopy |G|groupoid = 1.Believe it or not, you are reinventing BG! A groupoid can be reinterpreted as a space with vanishing homotopy groups above the first, and if you do this to the groupoid G, you get BG.More generally:
Recall that we can take a pointed space X and form a pointed space LX of loops in X that start and end at the basepoint. This clearly has
πn+1(X) = πn(LX)
so if X is connected and tame we'll have
|LX| = 1/|X|
Now with a little work you can make LX (or a space homotopy-equivalent to it!) into a topological group with composition of loops as the product.
And then it turns out that BLX is homotopy equivalent to X when X is connected. Conversely, given a topological group G, LBG is homotopy equivalent to G.
So what we're seeing is that topological groups and connected pointed spaces are secretly the same thing, at least from the viewpoint of homotopy theory. In topology, few things are as important as this fact.
But what's really going on here? Well, to go from a topological group G to a connected pointed space, you have to form BG, which has all the same homotopy groups but just pushed up one notch:
πn+1(BG) = πn(G)
And to go from a connected point space X to a topological group, you have to form LX, which has all the same homotopy groups but just pushed down one notch:
πn-1(LX) = πn(X)
This is actually the trick you are playing, in slight disguise.
And the real point is that a 1-object ω-groupoid can be reinterpreted as an ω-groupoid by forgetting about the object and renaming all the j-morphisms "(j-1)-morphisms".
See? When you finally get to the bottom of it, this "BG" business is just a silly reindexing game!!! Of course no textbook can admit this openly - partially because they don't talk about ω-groupoids.
>>So Euler characteristic is a lot like homotopy cardinality. But >>not many spaces have both well-defined homotopy cardinality and >>well-defined Euler characteristic. So they're like Jekyll and Hyde - >>you hardly ever see them in the same place at the same time, so you >>can't tell if they're really the same guy. >So, are they ever both defined but different?I don't recall any examples where they're both finite, but different. I know very few cases where they're both finite! How about the point? How about the circle? How about the 2-sphere? I leave you to ponder these cases.>>However, there are still challenging tests to the theory that homotopy >>cardinality and Euler characteristic are secretly the same. Here's a >>puzzle due to James Dolan. Consider a Riemann surface of genus g > 1. >>Such a surface has Euler characteristic 2 - 2g, but such a surface also >>has vanishing homotopy groups above the first, which implies that it's >>BG for G equal to its fundamental group. If homotopy cardinality and >>Euler characteristic were the same, this would imply >> >> |G| = 1/|BG| = 1/χ(S) = 1/(2 - 2g). >> >>But the fundamental group G is infinite! What's going on? >This doesn't seem too surprising. 1/(2 - 2g) is also infinite. >Just use the geometric series in reverse: > > 1/(2 - 2g) = (1/2) ∑i gi, > >which diverges since g > 1.Well, what I really want is a way of counting elements of the fundamental group of the surface S which gives me a divergent sum that I can cleverly sum up to get 1/(2 - 2g).
14) William J. Floyd and Steven P. Plotnick, Growth functions on Fuchsian groups and the Euler characteristic, Invent. Math. 88 (1987), 1-29.
15) R. I. Grigorchuk, Growth functions, rewriting systems and Euler characteristic, Mat. Zametki 58 (1995), 653-668, 798.
You can read more about Euler characteristic and homotopy cardinality here:
16) John Baez, Euler characteristic versus homotopy cardinality, lecture at the Fields Institute Program on Applied Homotopy Theory, September 20, 2003. Available in PDF form at http://www.math.ucr.edu/home/baez/cardinality/
© 2000 John Baez
baez@math.removethis.ucr.andthis.edu
|