# March 5, 1996 {#week74} Before continuing my story about higher-dimensional algebra, let me say a bit about gravity. Probably far fewer people study general relativity than quantum mechanics, which is partially because quantum mechanics is more practical, but also because general relativity is mathematically more sophisticated. This is a pity, because general relativity is so beautiful! Recently, I have been spending time on `sci.physics` leading an informal (nay, chaotic) "general relativity tutorial". The goal is to explain the subject with a minimum of complicated equations, while still getting to the mathematical heart of the subject. For example, what does Einstein's equation REALLY MEAN? It's been a lot of fun and I've learned a lot! Now I've gathered up some of the posts and put them on a web site: 1) John Baez et al, "General relativity tutorial", [`gr/gr.html`](http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/gr/gr.html) I hope to improve this as time goes by, but it should already be fun to look at. Let me also list a couple new papers on the loop representation of quantum gravity, dealing with ways to make volume and area into observables in quantum gravity: 2) Abhay Ashtekar and Jerzy Lewandowski, "Quantum Theory of Geometry I: Area Operators", 31 pages in LaTeX format, to appear in Classical and Quantum Gravity, preprint available as [`gr-qc/9602046`](https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9602046). Jerzy Lewandowski, "Volume and Quantizations", preprint available as [`gr-qc/9602035`](https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9602035). Roberto De Pietri and Carlo Rovelli, "Geometry Eigenvalues and Scalar Product from Recoupling Theory in Loop Quantum Gravity", 38 pages, 5 Postscript figures, uses RevTeX 3.0 and `epsfig.sty`, preprint available as [`gr-qc/9602023`](https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9602023). I won't say anything about these now, but see ["Week 55"](#week55) for some information on area operators. ------------------------------------------------------------------------ Okay, where were we? We had started messing around with sets, and we noted that sets and functions between sets form a category, called Set. Then we started messing around with categories, and we noted that not only are there "functors" between categories, there are things that ply their trade between functors, called "natural transformations". I then said that categories, functors, and natural transformations form a $2$-category. I didn't really say what a $2$-category is, except to say that it has objects, morphisms between objects, and $2$-morphisms between morphisms. Finally, I said that this pattern continues: $n\mathsf{Cat}$ forms an $(n+1)$-category. By the way, I said last time that $\mathsf{Set}$ was "the primordial category". Keith Ramsay reminded me by email that this can be misleading. There are other categories that act a whole lot like $\mathsf{Set}$ and can serve equally well as "the primordial category". These are called topoi. Poetically speaking, we can think of these as alternate universes in which to do mathematics. For more on topoi, see ["Week 68"](#week68). All I meant by saying that $\mathsf{Set}$ was "the primordial category" is that, if we start from $\mathsf{Set}$ and various categories of structures built using sets --- groups, rings, vector spaces, topological spaces, manifolds, and so on --- we can then abstract the notion of "category", and thus obtain $\mathsf{Cat}$. In the same sense, $\mathsf{Cat}$ is the primordial $2$-category, and so on. I mention this because it is part of a very important broad pattern in higher-dimensional algebra. For example, we will see that the complex numbers are the primordial Hilbert space, and that the category of Hilbert spaces is the primordial "2-Hilbert space", and that the $2$-category of 2-Hilbert spaces is the primordial "3-Hilbert space", and so on. This leads to a quantum-theoretic analog of the hierarchy of $n$-categories, which plays an important role in mathematical physics. But I'm getting ahead of myself! Let's start by considering a few examples of categories. I want to pick some examples that will lead us naturally to the main themes of higher-dimensional algebra. Beware: it will take us a while to get rolling. For a while --- maybe a few issues of This Week's Finds --- everything may seem somewhat dry, pointless and abstract, except for those of you who are already clued in. It has the flavor of "foundations of mathematics," but eventually we'll see these new foundations reveal topology, representation theory, logic, and quantum theory to be much more tightly interknit than we might have thought. So hang in there. For starters, let's keep the idea of "symmetry" in mind. The typical way to think about symmetry is with the concept of a "group". But to get a concept of symmetry that's really up to the demands put on it by modern mathematics and physics, we need --- at the very least --- to work with a *category* of symmetries, rather than a group of symmetries. To see this, first ask: what is a category with one object? It is a "monoid". The *usual* definition of a monoid is this: a set $M$ with an associative binary product and a unit element $1$ such that $a1 = 1a = a$ for all $a$ in $M$. Monoids abound in mathematics; they are in a sense the most primitive interesting algebraic structures. To check that a category with one object is "essentially just a monoid", note that if our category $\mathcal{C}$ has one object $x$, the set $\operatorname{Hom}(x,x)$ of all morphisms from $x$ to $x$ is indeed a set with an associative binary product, namely composition, and a unit element, namely $1_x$. (Actually, in an arbitrary category $\operatorname{Hom}(x,y)$ could be a class rather than a set. But let's not worry about such nuances.) Conversely, if you hand me a monoid $M$ in the traditional sense, I can easily cook up a category with one object $x$ and $\operatorname{Hom}(x,x) = M$. How about categories in which every morphism is invertible? We say a morphism $f\colon x\to y$ in a category has inverse $g\colon y\to x$ if $fg = 1_x$ and $gf = 1_y$. Well, a category in which every morphism is invertible is called a "groupoid". Finally, a group is a category with one object in which every morphism is invertible. It's both a monoid and a groupoid! When we use groups in physics to describe symmetry, we think of each element $g$ of the group $G$ as a "process". The element $1$ corresponds to the "process of doing nothing at all". We can compose processes $g$ and $h$ --- do $h$ and then $g$ --- and get the product $gh$. Crucially, every process $g$ can be "undone" using its inverse $g^{-1}$. We tend to think of this ability to "undo" any process as a key aspect of symmetry. I.e., if we rotate a beer bottle, we can rotate it back so it was just as it was before. We don't tend to think of SMASHING the beer bottle as a symmetry, because it can't be undone. But while processes that can be undone are especially interesting, it's also nice to consider other ones... so for a full understanding of symmetry we should really study monoids as well as groups. But we also should be interested in "partially defined" processes, processes that can be done only if the initial conditions are right. This is where categories come in! Suppose that we have a bunch of boxes, and a bunch of processes we can do to a bottle in one box to turn it into a bottle in another box: for example, "take the bottle out of box $x$, rotate it 90 degrees clockwise, and put it in box $y$". We can then think of the boxes as objects and the processes as morphisms: a process that turns a bottle in box $x$ to a bottle in box $y$ is a morphism $f\colon x\to y$. We can only do a morphism $f\colon x\to y$ to a bottle in box $x$, not to a bottle in any other box, so $f$ is a "partially defined" process. This implies we can only compose $f\colon x\to y$ and $g\colon u \to v$ to get $fg\colon x \to v$ if $y = u$. So: a monoid is like a group, but the "symmetries" no longer need be invertible; a category is like a monoid, but the "symmetries" no longer need to be composable! Note for physicists: the operation of "evolving initial data from one spacelike slice to another" is a good example of a "partially defined" process: it only applies to initial data on that particular spacelike slice. So dynamics in special relativity is most naturally described using groupoids. Only after pretending that all the spacelike slices are the same can we pretend we are using a group. It is very common to pretend that groupoids are groups, since groups are more familiar, but often insight is lost in the process. Also, one can only pretend a groupoid is a group if all its objects are isomorphic. Groupoids really are more general. Physicists wanting to learn more about groupoids might try: 3) Alan Weinstein, "Groupoids: unifying internal and external symmetry", available as `http://math.berkeley.edu/~alanw/Groupoids.ps` or `http://www.ams.org/notices/199607/weinstein.pdf` So: in contrast to a set, which consists of a static collection of "things", a category consists not only of objects or "things" but also morphisms which can viewed as "processes" transforming one thing into another. Similarly, in a $2$-category, the $2$-morphisms can be regarded as "processes between processes", and so on. The eventual goal of basing mathematics upon $\omega$-categories is thus to allow us the freedom to think of any process as the sort of thing higher-level processes can go between. By the way, it should also be very interesting to consider "$\mathbb{Z}$-categories" (where $\mathbb{Z}$ denotes the integers), having $j$-morphisms not only for $j = 0,1,2,\ldots$ but also for negative $j$. Then we may also think of any thing as a kind of process. How do the above remarks about groups, monoids, groupoids and categories generalize to the $n$-categorical context? Well, all we did was start with the notion of category and consider two sorts of requirement: that the category have just one object, or that all morphisms be invertible. A category with just one object --- a monoid --- could also be seen as a set with extra algebraic structure, namely a product and unit. Suppose we look at an $n$-category with just one object? Well, it's very similar: then we get a special sort of $(n-1)$-category, one with a product and unit! We call this a "monoidal $(n-1)$-category". I will explain this more thoroughly later, but let me just note that we can keep playing this game, and consider a monoidal $(n-1)$-category with just one object, which is a special sort of $(n-2)$-category, which we could call a "doubly monoidal $(n-2)$-category", and so on. This game must seem very abstract and mysterious when one first hears of it. But it turns out to yield a remarkable set of concepts, some already very familiar in mathematics, and it turns out to greatly deepen our notion of "commutativity". For now, let me simply display a chart of "$k$-tuply monoidal $n$-categories" for certain low values of $n$ and $k$: | | $n=0$ | $n=1$ | $n=2$ | | ----- | :--- | :--- | :--- | | $k=0$ | sets | categories | $2$-categories | | | | | | | $k=1$ | monoids | monoidal categories | monoidal $2$-categories | | | | | | | $k=2$ | commutative monoids | braided monoidal categories | braided monoidal $2$-categories | | | | | | | $k=3$ | " " | symmetric monoidal categories | weakly involutory monoidal $2$-categories | | | | | | | $k=4$ | " " | " " | strongly involutory monoidal $2$-categories | | | | | | | $k=5$ | " " | " " | " " | :$k$-tuply monoidal $n$-categories The quotes indicate that each column "stabilizes" past a certain point. If you can't wait to read more about this, you might try ["Week 49"](#week49) for more, but I will explain it all in more detail in future issues. What if we take an $n$-category and demand that all $j$-morphisms ($j > 0$) be invertible? Well, then we get something we could call an "$n$-groupoid". However, there are some important subtle issues about the precise sense in which we might want all $j$-morphisms to be invertible. I will have to explain that, too. Let me conclude, though, by mentioning something the experts should enjoy. If we define $n$-groupoids correctly, and then figure out how to define $\omega$-groupoids correctly, the homotopy category of $\omega$-groupoids turns out to be equivalent to the homotopy category of topological spaces. The latter category is something algebraic topologists have spent decades studying. This is one of the main ways $n$-categories are important in topology. Using this correspondence between $n$-groupoid theory and homotopy theory, the "stabilization" property described above is then related to a subject called "stable homotopy theory", and "$\mathbb{Z}$-groupoids" are a way of talking about "spectra" --- another important tool in homotopy theory. The above paragraph is overly erudite and obscure, so let me explain the gist: there is a way to think of a topological space as giving us an $\omega$-groupoid, and the $\omega$-groupoid then captures all the information about its topology that homotopy theorists find interesting. (I will explain in more detail how this works later.) If this is *all* $n$-category theory did, it would simply be an interesting language for doing topology. But as we shall see, it does a lot more. One reason is that, not only can we use $n$-categories to think about spaces, we can also use them to think about symmetries, as described above. Of course, physicists are very interested in space and also symmetry. So from the viewpoint of a mathematical physicist, one interesting thing about $n$-categories is that they *unify* the study of space (or spacetime) with the study of symmetry. I will continue along these lines next time and try to fill in some of the big gaping holes. To continue reading the "Tale of $n$-Categories", see ["Week 75"](#week75).