Our basic intuitions about mathematics are to some extent abstracted from our dealings with the everyday physical world [19]. The concept of a set, for example, formalizes some of our intuitions about piles of pebbles, herds of sheep and the like. These things are all pretty well described by classical physics, at least in their gross features. For this reason, it may seem amazing that mathematics based on set theory can successfully describe the microworld, where quantum physics reigns supreme. However, beyond the overall `surprising effectiveness of mathematics', this should not really come as a shock. After all, set theory is sufficiently flexible that any sort of effective algorithm for making predictions can be encoded in the language of set theory: even Peano arithmetic would suffice.
But, we should not be lulled into accepting the primacy of the category of sets and functions just because of its flexibility. The mere fact that we can use set theory as a framework for studying quantum phenomena does not imply that this is the most enlightening approach. Indeed, the famously counter-intuitive behavior of the microworld suggests that not only set theory but even classical logic is not optimized for understanding quantum systems. While there are no real paradoxes, and one can compute everything to one's heart's content, one often feels that one is grasping these systems `indirectly', like a nuclear power plant operator handling radioactive material behind a plate glass window with robot arms. This sense of distance is reflected in the endless literature on `interpretations of quantum mechanics', and also in the constant invocation of the split between `observer' and `system'. It is as if classical logic continued to apply to us, while the mysterious rules of quantum theory apply only to the physical systems we are studying. But of course this is not true: we are part of the world being studied.
To the category theorist, this raises the possibility that
quantum theory might make more sense when viewed, not from
the category of sets and functions, but within some other category:
for example , the category of Hilbert spaces and bounded
linear operators. Of course it is most convenient to define this
category and study it with the help of set theory. However, as we
have seen, the fact that Hilbert spaces are sets equipped with extra
structure and properties is almost a distraction when trying to
understand
, because its morphisms are not functions that
preserve this extra structure. So, we can gain a new understanding
of quantum theory by trying to accept
on its own terms,
unfettered by preconceptions taken from the category
. As
Corfield [10] writes: ``Category theory allows you to work
on structures without the need first to pulverise them into set
theoretic dust. To give an example from the field of architecture,
when studying Notre Dame cathedral in Paris, you try to understand how
the building relates to other cathedrals of the day, and then to earlier
and later cathedrals, and other kinds of ecclesiastical building.
What you don't do is begin by imagining it reduced to a pile
of mineral fragments.''
In this paper, we have tried to say quite precisely how some intuitions
taken from fail in
. Namely: unlike
,
is a
-category, and a monoidal category where the tensor product
is noncartesian. But, what makes this really interesting is that these
ways in which
differs from
are precisely the ways
it resembles
, the category of
-dimensional
manifolds and
-dimensional cobordisms going between these
manifolds. In general relativity these cobordisms represent
`spacetimes'. Thus, from the category-theoretic perspective, a
bounded linear operator between Hilbert spaces acts more like a
spacetime than a function. This not only sheds a new light
on some classic quantum quandaries, it also bodes well for the main
task of quantum gravity, namely to reconcile quantum theory with general
relativity.
At best, we have only succeeded in sketching a few aspects of the
analogy between and
. In
a more detailed treatment we would explain how both
and
are `symmetric monoidal categories with duals' -- a notion
which subsumes being a monoidal category and a
-category.
Moreover, we would explain how unitary topological quantum field
theories exploit this fact to this hilt. However, a discussion of
this can be found elsewhere [6], and it necessarily leads
us into deeper mathematical waters which are not of such immediate
philosophical interest. So, instead, I would like to conclude by
saying a bit about the progress people have made in learning to
think within categories other than
.
It has been known for quite some time in category theory that each category has its own `internal logic', and that while we can reason externally about a category using classical logic, we can also reason within it using its internal logic -- which gives a very different perspective. For example, our best understanding of intuitionistic logic has long come from the study of categories called `topoi', for which the internal logic differs from classical logic mainly in its renunciation of the principle of excluded middle [9,11,28]. Other classes of categories have their own forms of internal logic. For example, ever since the work of Lambek [18], the typed lambda-calculus, so beloved by theoretical computer scientists, has been understood to arise as the internal logic of `cartesian closed' categories. More generally, Lawvere's algebraic semantics allows us to see any `algebraic theory' as the internal logic of a category with finite products [21].
By now there are many textbook treatments of these ideas and
their ramifications, ranging from introductions that do not assume
prior knowledge of category theory [12,27],
to more advanced texts that do [7,16,20,24].
All this suggests that the time is ripe to try thinking about
physics using the internal logic of , or
, or
related categories. However, the textbook treatments and even
most of the research literature on category-theoretic logic
focus on categories where the monoidal structure is cartesian.
The study of logic within more general monoidal categories is
just beginning. More precisely, while generalizations of
`algebraic theories' to categories of this sort have been studied
for many years in topology and physics [22,25], it is
hard to find work that explicitly recognizes the relation of such
theories to the traditional concerns of logic, or even of quantum logic.
For some heartening counterexamples, see the work of Abramsky
and Coecke [1], and also of Mauri [26]. So, we can
only hope that in the future, more interaction between mathematics,
physics, logic and philosophy will lead to new ways of thinking about
quantum theory -- and quantum gravity -- that take advantage of
the internal logic of categories like
and
.
© 2004 John Baez
baez@math.removethis.ucr.andthis.edu